Posted by Keith Tidman
In his 1516 book Utopia,
the English statesman and writer Sir Thomas More summed up his imagined, idealised
vision of an island society in this manner:
Detail from the original frontispiece for More’s book Utopia |
‘Nobody owns anything but everyone
is rich — for what greater wealth can there be than cheerfulness, peace of mind,
and freedom from anxiety?’
A laconic, even breezy counterpoint to the imperfect and in
some cases heavily flawed dystopian societies that actually populated the
world — More’s utopia presenting a republic confronting much that was wrong in
the 16th century. More’s utopia promulgates
the uplifting notion that, despite humankind’s fallibilities, many ills of
society have remedies.
Two other writers, Daniel Defoe and Jonathan Swift, who wrote Robinson Crusoe and Gulliver’s Travels respectively, were both authors of popular 18th-century stories that took inspiration from the utopian principles of Thomas More.
Two other writers, Daniel Defoe and Jonathan Swift, who wrote Robinson Crusoe and Gulliver’s Travels respectively, were both authors of popular 18th-century stories that took inspiration from the utopian principles of Thomas More.
The word ‘utopia’, coined by More, is from the Greek,
meaning ‘no place’. Yet, it seems likely that More was also punning on a different word, pronounced identically, which applies
more aptly to history’s descriptions of utopia — like that captured in Plato’s Republic (of ‘philosopher-kings’ fame),
Tommaso Campanella’s City of the Sun,
and Francis Bacon’s New Atlantis — that
word being ‘eutopia’. The word is also of Greek origin, but signifies
‘good place’.
Some see utopias and eutopias alike as heralding the possibility of reforming present society toward some idealised end point — what Herbert Marcuse, the 20th-century German-American philosopher, referred to as ‘the end of utopia’, when ‘material and intellectual forces capable of achieving the transformation are technically present’.
Some see utopias and eutopias alike as heralding the possibility of reforming present society toward some idealised end point — what Herbert Marcuse, the 20th-century German-American philosopher, referred to as ‘the end of utopia’, when ‘material and intellectual forces capable of achieving the transformation are technically present’.
However, long ago, Aristotle pushed back against the concept of utopia as
an unattainable figment — a chimera. Later
political theorists have joined the criticism, notably More’s contemporary,
the Italian political philosopher and statesman Niccolò Machiavelli. In The Prince, Machiavelli concurs with More’s
notions of cynicism and corruption seen in society generally and in politics
specifically. As such, Machiavelli believed that the struggle for political
supremacy is conflictual, necessarily lacking morality — the ‘effective truth
of the thing’ in power politics. ‘Politics have no relation to morals’, he
stated bluntly. Machiavelli thus did not brook what he regarded as illusory
social orders like utopias.
Nonetheless, utopias are, in their intriguingly ambitious way,
philosophical, sociological, and political thought experiments. They promulgate
and proclaim norms that by implication reproachfully differ from all current
societies. They are both inspirational and aspirational. As H.G. Wells noted
in his 1905 novel, A Modern Utopia:
‘Our business here is to be
Utopian, to make vivid and credible, if we can, first this facet and then that,
of an imaginary whole and happy world’.
In that vein, many thinkers have taken their definitions to
the next level, offering concrete prescriptions: deconstructing society’s
shortcomings, and fleshing out blueprints for the improved social order
envisioned. These blueprints may include multiple
dimensions: political, economic, ecological, moral, educational, customs, judicial, familial,
values, communal, philosophical, and scientific and technological, among
others.
The 17th-century English philosopher Thomas Hobbes, however, paints a bleak dystopia, even in the highly reformed architecture of utopia:
‘For the laws of nature … of
themselves, without the terror of some power, to cause them to be observed, are
contrary to our natural passions’.
That is, given that the ‘natural condition of mankind’ is to incurably
and quarrelsomely seek ever more power, the civilizing effects of laws and
of governance are required to channel people’s energies and ambitions, and to constrain as necessary.
Yet legal constraints can reach too far: this kind of utopian theorizing lapses into a formula for authoritarianism. The German professor of literature Artur Blaim has summed up, as forthrightly as anyone, the suppressive nature associated with a political system of this kind as:
Yet legal constraints can reach too far: this kind of utopian theorizing lapses into a formula for authoritarianism. The German professor of literature Artur Blaim has summed up, as forthrightly as anyone, the suppressive nature associated with a political system of this kind as:
‘Utopias
die, utopianism does not’.
The apprehension, then, is that even in a declared utopia, powerful
leaders might coerce reluctant conformists to fit into a single mold. Dangerously
patriarchal, given possibly counterfactual evidence of what’s best for most.
Certainly, there have been occurrences — ‘utopian’ cults, cabals, compounds, religions, and even nation states’ political systems — where heavy-handed pressure to step in line has been administered and violence has erupted. In these scenarios, repressive measures — to preserve society’s structural demands — are at the expense of freedom and liberal drives. As Bertrand de Jouvenel, a 20th-century French philosopher, counseled, if somewhat hyperbolically:
Certainly, there have been occurrences — ‘utopian’ cults, cabals, compounds, religions, and even nation states’ political systems — where heavy-handed pressure to step in line has been administered and violence has erupted. In these scenarios, repressive measures — to preserve society’s structural demands — are at the expense of freedom and liberal drives. As Bertrand de Jouvenel, a 20th-century French philosopher, counseled, if somewhat hyperbolically:
‘There is a tyranny in every utopia.’
So, might ‘utopia’ be defined differently than any single
idealised end point, where ‘satisfied’ architects of utopia feel comfortable putting their
tools down, hinting ‘it’s the end of history’?
Or instead, might utopianism be better characterised as a dynamic process of change — of a perpetual becoming (emergence) — directed in the search of ever-better conditions? The key to utopianism is thus its catalytic allure: the uninterrupted exploration, trying out, and readjustment of modalities and norms.
As the
20th-century German philosopher Ernst Bloch pointed out,
‘Expectation, hope and intention, directed towards the
possibility which has not yet arrived, constitute not only a fundamental property
of the human consciousness but also … a fundamental determination at the heart
of objective reality itself’.
6 comments:
Fritjof Capra writes, 'To explain something means, ultimately, to show how it is connected to everything else.' He is speaking about an infinity relations in this world — while we ourselves are finite.
When we think on our own finitude, we understand that the greatest number of relations lie beyond our power to explain, and beyond our control. This means that we should be wary of totalising urges, which seek — impossibly — to conquer infinite relations. Where we strive for an unreachable mastery, unintended consequences are bound to disrupt our ambitions, and set the bar for control even higher — impossibly, unnaturally higher.
This is the peril of utopia. The requirement is rather a humble compassion for our fellow human beings. I once visited what was meant to be Pol Pot's agrarian utopia, when the country was still at war.
Yes, I think Pol Pot is a good example, actually. There seems to be an inherent authoritarianism in the utopian ideal - after all, it supposes itself to be the best and shuts down alternatives. On the other hand, as Keith says in this thoughtful piece, if a utopian ideal is seen merely as an alternative model that provides ideas and strategies for improving our 'present place', then surely it should retain a legitimate role in our thinking.
As for the ‘peril’ of utopia, I would agree, Thomas, that striving for ‘unreachable mastery’ risks leading to calamitous consequences. On the macro scale of nation states, vain attempts at ideological purity have found expression in history’s ‘isms’. On the micro scale of, say, cults and compounds, the ardent chase for purity — and for idealised social order, to which everyone is required to conform — not untypically ends catastrophically. At both the macro and micro level, Jouvenel wasn’t too far from centre in declaring, ‘There is a tyranny in every utopia’. Though just how tyrannical varies. But although there must be caution (and unpretentiousness), the pursuit of something better is, as Martin hints, an arguably noble and necessary ambition. For which, perhaps, there is no alternative; inertia, drawn from either fear or self-satisfaction, is surely unacceptable. After all, the churn of our striving, no matter how imprudent at times, is ultimately and fundamentally what spurs progress.
I fear that our progress may be counter-productive. Not all of it! But more than we think.
Progress for one means decline for other, very often...
The spiking inequality -- across all sorts of economic, social, and governance models -- would seem to bear out your point, Tessa. But I wonder if appearances are slightly deceptive. That is, resources aren't necessarily zero-sum, even if that's the perception. Rather, what I think makes the difference between the richest and the poorest -- what gives rise to the (mis)perception of zero-sum resources, all the while in face of the reality of resources terribly unequally spread around -- is in actuality a difference in power and control over the self-serving mechanisms that drive national policymaking.
Post a Comment