The Philosophical Society of England has long championed
'philosophy in schools', and over the years has published several
articles on the topic. In 1952, Bernard
Youngman's strategy for a philosophical education was copious
amounts of Bible study, whereas nowadays Philosophy in Schools is
portrayed as a kind of antidote to religion, a position both explored
and advocated at book length by Stephen Law in The War for
Children's Minds (also reviewed
on the Philosopher website.)
But at least Law would agree with Youngman that the
educator's task involves leading 'the young untutored mind towards love
of wisdom and knowledge'. And both follow the philosophical principle
that the teacher (in Youngman's words) "must value freedom of thought
and revere independence of mind; he must at all times be as Plato so
succinctly put it - midwife to his pupils' thoughts".
In the dark days of Madame Thatcher,
and the UK of the 1980s, when everyone 'knew the price of everything
and the value of nothing', philosophy was out of fashion at all levels
of education. But these days Philosophy is undergoing something of a
resurgence, particularly in UK schools. Not for nothing did that
cynical marketing phenomenon, Harry Potter, designate his first task as
'the search for the Philosopher's Stone'. Because, philosophy, however
interpreted, has something about it that is appealing to children,
intellectuals and hard-nosed accountants alike.
And even if it is sometimes not quite clear which group is
driving it, certainly there are now schools dotted all around Britain
dipping at least a small toe into philosophy, from small rural
Primaries to large urban Grammars. There are a lot of deep philosophy
of education and teaching methodology issues raised by these projects.
In particular, philosophy like this (unlike the elitist and stultifying
French /Philosophy Bac') is part of the shift away from learning
content to towards 'thinking skills', and indeed listening and
communication skills. Philosophy for children in this sense is just
part of a "creative curriculum", made up out of Music, Dance, and the
Arts.
One school that has made a particular campaign out of the
approach is a small London primary school called Gallions (in E6) which
claims that philosophy has cultivated and encouraged creativity,
empathy and a sense of self-worth throughout the school. After
reinventing itself in this philosophy-inspired way, it claims to have
made enormous progress.
"Regular practice in thinking and reasoning together has had
an extraordinary impact on learning, on relationships, and on mutual
respect within and beyond the school gates", Gallions says in one of
its innovative (read expensive) publicity materials.
Gallions claims to have found the holy grail of education -
active, creative, democratic -somewhere in the, by now fairly
well-worn, methods of Matthew Lipman, a professor of philosophy in the
United States, branded as 'P4C', along with more recent help from
SAPERE a sort of British off-shoot busy selling courses in its methods
(including 'masters' degrees at Oxford Brookes University).
Made into a commercial brand by Lipman, 'P4C' is an
educational approach which promises to turn children and young people
into effective, critical and creative thinkers and help them to take
responsibility for their own learning 'in a creative and collaborative
environment'.
The method invariably involves a warm-up or 'thinking game',
featuring what is rather grandly called 'the introduction of the
stimulus' but might more prosaically be counted as the presentation of
the lesson's theme. The group are invited to discuss and eventually
decide exactly what questions they want to discuss related to this
theme.
For younger children, 'thinking games' like these are
advocated.
Bring an object in (Use a prop): In this, an
everyday object is placed in the middle of a circle of children, and
everybody in turn given an opportunity to ask the object a
question.
Random words: This time, again working in a circle,
each child says a word which must be unconnected to the last word
spoken. If someone thinks there is a connection between the words they
call out 'challenge!' and must explain the link.
(If you think these are not much of 'games', you should try the
ordinary lessons )
Naturally , schools being schools, philosophy starts off with
'rules'. There are rules about speaking - not talking when someone else
is talking, about not laughing at other people's ideas - and rules
about 'listening - letting people finish, taking 'thinking time' to
consider other people's ideas before speaking, and connecting new
contributions to points previously made. All this is both virtuous and
very practical. If children learn little else at school , they learn
ways of intreating with others. Too often, the school environment
discourages discussion and collaboration in favour of rigid
distinctions between 'right and wrong' points of view and hierarchies
of knowledge.
In all this, the teacher is there not to teach, but only as a
source of information or occasionally a 'referee' ensuring both
fairness and perhaps encouraging (assuming, which is a big assumption,
that they are able to distinguish) the most interesting lines of
discussion from the rest. In short, they act as as 'facilitators' for
the groups' learning. 'In a community of enquiry all the knowledge to
be absorbed comes from the children', preach the P4C guidance notes.
The aim is that the children teach each other. Their choices are aid to
dominate the entire process: they construct the questions they consider
interesting about the stimulus, they choose the question they wish to
debate, and they decide in what way they want to contribute to the
discussion.
As a consequence of all this freedom to decide what to talk
about, the adherents of philosophy for children claim that the classes
learn how to think and express their thoughts in new and often dramatic
ways.
Secondly, as children listen to and learn from each other,
they are said to practise and develop 'communication skills, such as
empathy, patience and generosity. Both individually and as a group they
become attentive and supportive of each other.
Regular doses of 'P4C' are claimed to enable even the shyest
children to develop such speaking and listening skills. 'They learn
that, in order for them to be heard when they have something to say,
they have to listen, and listen carefully, to what others say. The
cognitive challenge represented by the stimulus, the facilitation that
constantly challenges understanding and pushes for greater depth and
clarity, and the thrill of being listened to with interest, causes them
to develop their vocabulary and grammar. Children are generally seen to
increase the length and complexity of their contributions over time.'
(From a P4C Handout for in-service teacher training edited by Lisa
Naylor.)
They also acquire a vocabulary for expressing unhappiness,
discomfort or frustration, which leads to negotiating with other
children instead of expressing their feelings through physical means.
Playground interactions change.
All this leads to children spending more time reflecting on
ideas, and becoming generally more thoughtful and articulate. The
ability to reflect on one's own thinking is, after all, we are told, a
feature of very able people. And so, the children's improved
self-esteem translates into increased academic achievement.
Mind you, if the approach was really as successful and as
transformative as its advocates claim, it would seem a pity to restrict
it to the drip-feed of accredited trainers and special conferences.
After all, the ideas are as old as the slopes of Mount Olympus, and
materials abound promising ways to implement them.
Yet, the would-be philosophy teachers are encouraged to think
that introducing creativity, much less philosophy into the classroom,
requires additional training - more expertise, not less! Since the UK
government privatised education, the Internet is full of sites (such as
Independent
Thinking Limited) offering 'experts' in education, usually seen as
a kind of branch of business management. In places such as this, the
experts, fresh from successful careers as insurance salesmen or racing
car drivers boast of their outstanding qualities under pictures of
themselves on yachts.
Attitude, creativity, taking
responsibility, genius, goal setting and much more ? all the stuff that
he had never been told before but was beginning to wish he had. More to
the point, he began to formulate the idea of working with young people
to take these ideas into schools around the country.
- As one teacher trainer puts it. No wonder that all too often the
claims made for P4C turn out to be inflated, and that the children
describing how they have benefited seem to be repeating new educational
mantras rather than finding their own authentic voices.
This all goes against the original 'Socratic' principle that
the teacher stays in the background, only occasionally asserting
themselves if they feel either that the discussion has left the
philosophical arena completely - or alternatively, to encourage further
consideration fo an aspect that may have been raised but is not being
followed up by the others. They act as 'chairmen' of a debate, not as
sources of new information or adjudicators, both roles which rapidly
lead to the class becoming passive in the process.
But if school teachers find it difficult to stay in the
background and give up their role as final adjudicator, (few teachers
indeed have this knack) it is equally the problem for philosophy in
Higher Education too. How to democratise and stimulate philosophical
debate is very much the themes of recent work on Philosophy for 'big
children' in universities and colleges these days - particularly those
taking philosophy as a foundation course for a more specialised degree.
In the 1990s I was myself involved in research, under George MacDonald
Ross of Leeds University (nowadays part of the so-called '
Higher Education Academy').
Here, tactics such as 'proctorials', which are discussion groups
structured in a very similar way to the 'P4C groups reign supreme.
Because philosophy with children and Philosophy, 'with a
capital P', in seminar groups, shares many of the same characteristics.
There is, first of all, a wish to stimulate the group into active
discussion of an issue, and that requires 'the stimulus'. Puzzling
problems and paradoxes are often attractive to students, whereas
children may prefer more 'concrete' examples.
Whatever method is used, the important thing is to recognise
that the problems are triggers, not material in themselves, just as
philosophy should be a process, not a body of material to be passively
learned.
One secondary school teacher, Michael Brett, who introduced
philosophy to his classes (with children between 10 and 13) with books
of short philosophical problems, found that the ones which worked best
with school students were ones where 'pure philosophers' would refuse
to go, such as the economic ones in (my own book)
101 Philosophy
Problems, featuring eminently 'concrete' issues such as the price
of stamps, potatoes etc., alongside more traditional philosophy
problems represented however as secular puzzles, such as the barber who
couldn't cut his own hair (Russell's paradox) and so on.
Another book Michael Brett tried with his classes, published
in America, called
The Book of Questions, had, as one would
hope, lots of questions - most of which were ethical and which he
thought they'd like, but ihis experience was that children basically
preferred the 'barber', the 'stamps and potatoes'...
As he later summed it up, this seemed to be because:
children like to see a point to what they are
thinking about: understanding economics, money etc., or the interest of
puzzles. They aren't that bothered about questions that bear little on
their lives - as they see them.
When Lisa Naylor says (see article at
The Philosopher) that philosophy encourages children
to become producers of surprisingly abstract thought, it has to be
remembered that these abstract issues have first of all been made
'concrete' by being brought into the classroom as tape recordings or
even simple objects.
This fact has to be borne in mind when imagining that
philosophy for children is an opportunity to introduce questions with
no particular answer, debates with no particular purpose. Philosophy is
not just anything goes... Of course, it might be too early to ask, that
this should also be borne in mind for philosophers at all levels.
Martin Cohen